(Joint work with Assaf Hasson [HG].)
Take a computer scientist perspective on the notion of a model category, something fashionable some ten years ago. By definition, a model category is a category with three distinguished classes of morphisms satisfying diagram chasing axioms.
What is a category ? Well, it is a directed = oriented graph, with a class of distinguished subgraphs called commutative diagrams such that every string of consequitive arrows → → ... → fits into a unique distinguished triangle subgraph
. "Three distinguished classes of morphisms" -- its edges = arrows are labelled by combinations of three labels (c), (w) and (f).
The axioms? Rules for diagram chasing: adding an arrow or a label to the part of graph you already constructed (as a computer scientist, you can not really have the whole of an infinite graph, can you?). For example, axiom M2 of model categories says that any arrow is equal to a composition
What a computer scientist would do now? Use these rules for a script generating a dungeon for a roguelijk: rooms are objects, doors are arrows/morphisms and labels, random seed is a labelled commutative diagram in a model category.
Keeping track of commutative diagrams is a mess -- the morphisms sets between even moderate objects are usually unlistable [Gr]. So s/he assumes all diagrams commute, in of the script
But are these rules consistent? Is there a model category where all the diagrams commute---in other words, is there a partial order admitting structure of a model category and say there is an arrow with no labels?
A set theorist quickly finds some: there is one for every regular cardinal including
. As they say, a model category is a tool to prove results about its homotopy category, and let's describe the homotopy categories of such model categories.
Objects of are clasess of countable sets; for
objects of
's are (arbitrary) classes of sets of size
.
in
iff every
exists
such that
is finite.
in
iff for every
exists
of
such that
A homotopy theorist tells that the ((cwf)-labelled) model category wrt its homotopy category is akin to a category wrt its isomorphism classes of objects: for purposes of a good ("meaningful") question, isomorphic, resp. homotopic, objects are aways equivalent, but to prove anything you need to pick representatives and work in the category, resp. the category with its cwf-labels. A typical task is to calculate some homotopy invariants, e.g. some properties of homotopy categories or of canonical functors from the homotopy categories.
A functor is another word for an order preserving (or order reversing); it is canonical iff "it depends on the category itself only", says the homotopy theorist. S/he means that for any automorphism
of the partial order ("category"),
are "equivalent"; a logician (almost correctly) understands it to say "definable in the language of a category in an strong enough logic".
The easiest canonical functor to think of is perhaps
And then the revisited continuum hypothesis theorem of Shelah:
for many ---is a homotopy invariant continuum hypothesis. The equality

But a set theorist may ask a simpler question first: are homotopy categories dense (as partial orders)?
is dense;
is not;
is dense iff
is not measurable.
Proof :
means that I is a
-closed ideal on
;
is maximal such (in
) iff there is nothing strictly
-between
and
. Finally, note that there is nothing between
implies that for every
, there is nothing in between
and
implies that at least one of these inequalities is strict.
To summarise: Amazingly, this language of a labelled category has "sufficient generality to cover in a uniform way the different homotopy theories encountered" if "properly, often non-obviously, developed" to express "a large number of arguments that [are] formally similar to well-known ones in algebraic topology", and that these "homotopy theories" are the (non-obvious) structure the homotopy category does inherit. [Qu] An optimist may hope that thereby the homotopy theory shall "contribute new insights to old Cantorian problems of the scale of infinities" [Ma], e.g. one indeed finds in set theory "a large number of arguments that [are] formally similar to well-known ones in algebraic topology".
As always in mathematics, there's an interplay between "too much structure, too much information" and "too little information, too little to say". A model category is a means of forgetting some of the "too much information" while (hopefully) not getting lost in the "too little to say". A key fact in this construction is that it collapses the power function, probably, the greatest creator of chaos in set theory. But, maybe because this is the whole point of model categories, it also creates some replacement (in the form, e.g., (c)-labelled arrows and (wf)-arrows
which turn out to be closely related to Shelah's covering families and numbers), which turn out to be of interest.
[HG] M. Gavrilovich and A. Hasson. Exercises de style: A homotopy theory for set theory.Part I and II.
[Gr] M. Gromov, Ergobrain. On Categories and Functors, p.69.
[Ma] Yu. Manin, Foundations as Superstructure. (Reflections of a practicing mathematician).
[Qu] D. Quillen, Homotopical Algebra. Available online.
[Sh:460] S. Shelah, The Generalized Continuum Hypothesis revisited.